Mon. May 20th, 2024

Third Circuit Holds that a Nonviolent Offender May Not Be Stripped of Second Amendment Rights.

Range v. Attorney General

As gun rights have evolved in the United States, the Supreme Court has moved away from a means-end test and adopted a history-and-tradition framework for evaluating Second Amendment challenges.1 This framework requires that any firearm regulation be “consistent with this Nation’s historical tradition of firearm regulation.”2 Numerous federal courts have already used this test to swiftly strike down over a dozen state and federal laws cabining gun possession rights.3 Lower courts presented with challenges to felon-in-possession laws, however, have greatly differed over how to analogize firearm regulations of the Founding to the present.4 Recently, in Range v. Attorney General,5 the Third Circuit applied this test, as required under New York State Rifle & Pistol Association v. Bruen,6 and determined there were not historical analogues to stripping a nonviolent offender7 of his Second Amendment rights. The decision — the first of a federal circuit applying 18 U.S.C. § 922(g)(1) after Bruen8 — has raised questions about whether felon-in-possession laws are still “presumptively lawful.”9 Range narrowly decided that firearm disenfranchisement of convicted individuals “like Range” is unconstitutional.10 The Third Circuit’s inchoate “like Range” test underscores that the history-and-tradition test is difficult for evaluating challenges to felon-in-possession laws. By failing to directly grapple with the history-and-tradition test’s indeterminacy, the Third Circuit missed an opportunity to adopt a more definite standard of dangerousness as the “touchstone.”11

In August of 1995, Bryan Range pleaded guilty to one count of making a false statement to obtain food stamp assistance, in violation of title 62, section 481(a) of the Pennsylvania Consolidated Statutes.12 Mr. Range, around the time of the offense, earned about $300 per week.13 Mr. Range’s wife, Mrs. Range, filled out an application for food stamps, and on the application, Mr. Range’s income was omitted.14 Mr. Range accepted responsibility for the omission on the application.15

At that time, Mr. Range’s false statement was classified as a first-degree misdemeanor, punishable by a maximum of five years’ im­prisonment, under Pennsylvania law.16 Consequently, his conviction triggered the application of § 922(g)(1),17 but Mr. Range maintained that he was not informed by the prosecutor or judge that his pleading would result in a firearms possession ban.18 Unaware that he was barred, Mr. Range attempted to purchase a gun twice.19 He was unsuccessful both times, and upon further research, he realized his nonviolent conviction precluded him from possessing a gun.20

Mr. Range, alleging that § 922(g)(1) violated his Second Amendment rights, filed suit in the District Court for the Eastern District of Pennsylvania.21 Judge Pratter looked to the Third Circuit’s test in Binderup v. Attorney General22 to determine whether a crime is so serious as to warrant a ban on a felon’s possession of firearms. Judge Pratter found one factor — cross-jurisdictional consensus about the seriousness of crime — weighed in favor of the government.23 This was sufficient for the government to prevail at step one, so the court granted summary judgment for the government.24 Mr. Range appealed.25

The Third Circuit affirmed.26 In a per curiam opinion, Judges Shwartz, Krause, and Roth held that § 922(g)(1), as applied to Mr. Range, was constitutional.27 Between Mr. Range’s appeal and the Third Circuit hearing the case, the Supreme Court decided Bruen. Establishing a history-and-tradition test, Bruen abrogated the Third Circuit’s seriousness test from Binderup.28 The panel applied the Bruen history-and-tradition test — surveying the historical record of felon-in-possession laws in England and in the Founding era — which first looks at whether the Second Amendment covers the regulated conduct or individual and then second at whether there are historical analogues to the regulation.29 The Third Circuit determined that “§ 922(g)(1) is consistent with the Nation’s history and tradition of firearm regulation.”30 Mr. Range successfully petitioned for the case to be reheard en banc.31

The Third Circuit, sitting en banc, reversed and remanded.32 Writing for the majority, Judge Hardiman33 applied the Bruen two-step test.

First, the majority determined that the Second Amendment applied to Mr. Range, notwithstanding his nonviolent misdemeanor conviction.34 The majority acknowledged that District of Columbia v. Heller,35 McDonald v. City of Chicago,36 and Bruen in dicta stated that only “law-abiding citizens,” not “the people” writ large, are protected under the Second Amendment, but the majority discussed how “the people” is used not only in the Second Amendment but also throughout the Constitution.37 If Mr. Range were not included as “the people” in the Second Amendment context, then he would be precluded from other rights as well.38 The majority also found that limiting Second Amendment rights to only those who are “law-abiding, responsible citizens” would be too vague and broad.39 The majority ultimately held that Mr. Range was one of “the people” whom the Second Amendment protects.40 Next, the Third Circuit concluded its analysis of Bruen’s first step by ruling that § 922(g)(1) regulates Second Amendment conduct, and that Mr. Range’s desire to possess firearms to hunt and for self-defense fell within the scope of the Second Amendment right under Heller.41

Second, the majority looked at whether § 922(g)(1) is a firearm regulation consistent with the nation’s history and tradition.42 The government relied on the dicta in Heller saying that there is a “longstanding” history of felon-in-possession laws, Justice Kavanaugh’s concurrence in Bruen stating that felon-in-possession laws are “presumptively lawful,” and the 1961 amendments to the Federal Firearms Act43 to support its contention that there is a history and tradition of felon-in-possession regulations.44at 103–06. The majority found this support unconvincing because the “longstanding” firearm regulation initially only applied to violent offenders, which Mr. Range was not, and because the “1961 iteration of § 922(g)(1)” was passed too recently (that is, 170 years after the ratification of the Second Amendment) to be “longstanding.”45 The government also pointed to historical firearm laws that disen­franchised those who were distrusted — Loyalists, Native Americans, Quakers, Catholics, and Blacks — but the majority determined that Mr. Range was not part of a similar group like those regulated in the Founding era.46 The majority also concluded that the government’s argument that even nonviolent offenses were considered serious and punishable by death was not related to the issue in front of them.47 Lastly, the majority held that the government’s citation to persuasive authorities was unconvincing because those opinions were handed down before Bruen abrogated prior tests.48 Therefore, the court ruled that the government did not meet its burden of establishing that § 922(g)(1), as applied to Mr. Range, was consistent with the history and tradition of American firearms regulation.49 The Third Circuit reversed the judgment of the district court and remanded so that the district court could grant declaratory judgment in favor of Mr. Range.50

Judge Porter concurred.51 He wrote separately to offer reasoning as to why there were no historical laws like § 922(g)(1).52

Judge Ambro, joined by Judges Greenaway, Jr., and Montgomery-Reeves, also concurred.53 Judge Ambro emphasized that § 922(g)(1) remained “presumptively lawful” as a mechanism of regulating those who are a threat to society.54

Judge Shwartz, joined by Judge Restrepo, dissented.55 She critiqued the majority’s treatment of precedent and historical analogues to § 922(g)(1). She also argued there was a tradition of regulating those deemed to be disloyal or disrespectful of the law.56

Judge Krause also dissented.57 She underscored that the historical record supports disarming those who disrespect the law and posited that the majority could have made a narrower ruling.58

Lastly, Judge Roth also dissented.59 She argued that § 922(g)(1) is consistent with historical firearm regulations.60

Range, unprecedentedly, held there is not a historical basis for disenfranchising a nonviolent offender, arguably “without articulating any principles mediating historical and modern laws.”61 The court reached the right conclusion that Mr. Range should not be barred from possessing firearms, but the majority’s narrow “like Range” test neglected to provide any guidance about “[w]hat specifically is it about Range that exempts him — and going forward, those ‘like [him]’ — from § 922(g)(1)’s enforcement.”62 As Judge Krause identified, if the “like Range” test is about whether the underlying conviction was for a nonviolent offense or whether the convicted individual has exhibited law-abiding behavior, then this standard is severely flawed.63 If, on the other hand, the “like Range” test is really about dangerousness, the court has punted on adopting this standard.

The majority notably did not rely on Mr. Range’s argument “that because ‘there is no historical tradition of disarming nonviolent felons,’ dangerousness is the ‘touchstone.’”64 The majority found that it “need not decide this dispute today because the Government did not carry its burden to provide a historical analogue to permanently disarm someone like Range, whether grounded in dangerousness or not.”65 Rather than set forth an indeterminate “like Range” standard, the Court should have interpreted § 922(g)(1) as analogous to historical firearm regulations of those who were perceived to be “dangerous.” Adopting a “dangerousness” framework, which comports with Bruen, would provide courts with a clearer way to analogize § 922(g) challenges, which could allow for more individuals with criminal records to regain their Second Amendment rights.

Bruen required the Range court to analogize Mr. Range’s nonviolent offense to historical regulations of similar conduct.66 According to scholars, there is a long tradition of regulating gun ownership of those who were deemed to be dangerous, disloyal, and untrustworthy.67 Importantly, “there is no historical justification for completely and forever depriving peaceable citizens — even nonviolent felons — of the right to keep and bear arms.”68 The majority correctly held that there is no historical basis for disenfranchising Mr. Range. Mr. Range’s conduct should certainly not be seen as being dangerous or disloyal, and his one-time criminal offense for food stamp fraud should not render him as permanently non-law-abiding. The fact that the opinions in Range drew upon the same history and reached different conclusions underscores the challenge of interpreting historical analogues.69 While historical interpretation will often be debated, a dangerousness framework can provide clearer guidance on how judges should analogize modern Second Amendment regulations to those of the past. Judges, then, could more uniformly analyze the permissible scope of § 922(g)(1). Consequently, courts could rule that more individuals with criminal re­cords, such as Mr. Range, should regain their Second Amendment rights.

The court’s lack of unanimity on how to interpret historical analogues may speak to a definitional issue — in which case, solely relying upon concepts like “violent” and “law-abiding” may be misplaced. As Judge Krause already articulated, interpreting the “like Range” test to mean “law-abiding” or nonviolent is “confounding” and “unworkable.”70 For one, considering a convicted person to be law-abiding is indeed counterintuitive.71 Judge Krause also underscored the difficulty in classifying what a violent crime is.72 Judge Ambro’s “threat to society” framework73 is similarly faulty because such a standard is seemingly arbitrary. For example, are “thieves,” as Judge Ambro posited,74 really a threat to society? Is a shoplifter? If so, Mr. Range, who was convicted of fraud, could be a thief. In fact, under Judge Ambro’s formulation, most white-collar offenders75 would be barred from firearm possession. However, there is no history before the 1960s that supports disenfranchising those who are “nonviolent.”76 In contrast, focusing on dangerousness, rather than on the overinclusive and indeterminate concepts of “violence” and “law-abiding” to disenfranchise those who are threats to society, aligns more closely with the history of firearm regulations. Moreover, defining a violent offense is also a “political act” that is laden with racism and classism.77 “Dangerousness” arguably can be determined through more standardized metrics.

By framing the history-and-tradition test as an inquiry into “dangerousness,” courts would not have to rely only on subjective78 determinations. Furthermore, courts would not have to rely on an individual’s criminal record, which would be a welcome departure since a violent con­viction is not a reliable predictor of future dangerousness.79 Data reveal that individuals who were released from state prison for drug offenses were more likely to be rearrested for a violent offense than were individuals released for homicide or sexual assault.80 The evidence shows that “people convicted of violent and sexual offenses are actually among the least likely to be rearrested.”81 A person who was convicted for a violent offense is not inherently “dangerous” once released back into society.82 Thus, a conviction is not a reliable predictor of future dangerousness.

Rather, there is a body of research that reveals what factors are and are not accurate predictors of future “dangerousness.”83 Data-informed determinations of “dangerousness” can serve as guidelines for judges when ascertaining whether a specific individual with a criminal conviction or a class of individuals with the same criminal conviction has Second Amendment rights. Although far from perfect,84 risk assessment tools can be used to provide a more objective (i.e., data-driven and consistent) evaluation of who may be dangerous.85 Demographic factors like age, for example, have historically been reliable predictors of future violent convictions.86 Courts, however, must be cognizant that risk assessment tools have been imbued with systemic racism.87

These factors can also help distinguish why certain convicted offenders, such as domestic abusers, maybe should be treated differently. For example, there is some evidence that ties firearm possession and a history of domestic violence to future dangerousness.88 Thus, notions of “dangerousness” can ease concerns held by those like Judges Krause and Shwartz, who worried that under the “like Range” test all felon-in-possession laws are essentially unlawful. Though flawed, data-informed notions of dangerousness can guide courts in determining which individuals with criminal records still have Second Amendment rights.

While the holding of Range comports with Bruen’s history-and-tradition test, the “like Range” standard provides little guidance for courts on how to analogize historical laws to § 922(g)(1).89 Until the Supreme Court clarifies the extent to which felon-in-possession laws are lawful, or overturns the Bruen history-and-tradition test, courts can and should evaluate modern felon-in-possession laws through the framework of dangerousness. But even when considering “dangerousness” as part of a Bruen history-and-tradition analysis, courts should be careful to remain critical, ensuring that such assessments do not reflect race or class biases. If courts adopt and vigilantly apply a dangerousness framework, many individuals with criminal convictions can have their Second Amendment rights rightfully restored under Bruen. source


Range v. AG and the Shifting Unconstitutionality of Gun Regulation in the US

On June 6, 2023, an en banc panel of the United States Court of Appeals for the Third Circuit ruled that 18 U.S.C. §922(g)(1), the “felon in possession of a firearm” statute, is unconstitutional as applied to one individual, Bryan Range. While the decision purports to be “a narrow one[,]” the rationale that underpins the decision calls into question whether statutes prohibiting those convicted of crimes punishable by more than one year in prison continue to pass constitutional muster. This article summarizes the series of events and decisions that led to Range, explains why the Range decision has important and broad implications on society, and predicts where courts may ultimately draw the line in the burgeoning struggle between Second Amendment rights and firearm regulation.

As to the case at hand, Range’s offense was about as innocuous as a crime that triggers the felon in possession statute can be. In 1995, Range, who at the time earned between $9.00 and $9.50 per hour while raising three children, underreported his income to qualify for food stamps. Range received the food stamps and when his false underreporting was discovered, had been improperly enriched by $2,458. Range served three years’ probation without incident.

While Range did not spend any time in prison, the crime of making false statements in order to obtain food stamps could have been punishable for up to five years imprisonment under the relevant Pennsylvania statute. Therefore, pursuant to§922(g)(1), which strips felons of their right to possess firearms  if they face more than one year in prison (or in certain circumstances, those convicted of a state misdemeanor with a potential sentence of more than two years), Range was forever ineligible to own a gun. Range purports to have learned about this restriction for the first time when he attempted to purchase a deer-hunting rifle in 1998.

Prior to the US Supreme Court’s decision in New York State Rifle & Pistol Association, Inc. v. Bruen, and generally speaking, for the 61 years since the current version of §922(g) has been codified, an analysis of Range’s case would have required some discussion of the means-ends scrutiny of the law at issue. That is to say in the basest terms, whether the challenged firearm law struck an appropriate balance between the Second Amendment right of the felon versus the need for public safety. Since the US Supreme Court’s decision in United States v. Heller, the Third Circuit Court of Appeals performed this analysis using what it called a “multifactored seriousness inquiry.” Under that test, the government probably could not strip an individual of his or her right to possess a firearm for jaywalking but could (and obviously did), strip people of their Second Amendment rights for things like making false statements to the government.

Both parties in Range conceded that the seriousness inquiry is kaput. Instead, and as set forth in Bruen, “the government may not simply posit that the [firearms] regulation promotes an important interest. Rather, the government must demonstrate that the regulation is consistent with this Nation’s historical tradition of firearm regulation.” Stated differently, whether a firearm restriction comports with the Second Amendment is no longer dependent on whether the law makes good policy sense or promotes an important need but rather whether a comparator to the regulation can be found in this Nation’s historical firearm laws.

To perform this analysis, the Court held that lower courts must determine whether the firearm restriction is consistent with this Nation’s history and tradition by reasoning through analogy, which the Court notes is a “commonplace task for any lawyer or judge.” To provide further guidance, the Court stated that the historical analysis requires determining whether the historical regulation and the present-day regulation are “relevantly similar,” adding, “a green truck and a green hat are relevantly similar if one’s metric is ‘things that are green.’  They are not relevantly similar if the applicable metric is ‘things you can wear.’”

Notably, Bruen involved a challenge to a New York State statute that required an individual to show a “special need for self-protection distinguishable from that of the general community” in order to obtain a license to carry a handgun in public. While holding the New York statute unconstitutional, the Court provided no real guidance as to how this analysis would differ – if at all – when considering the §922(g) felon in possession statutes. To say this caused issues in the lower courts would be an understatement.

For instance, in U.S. v. Bullock, the United States District Court for the Southern District of Mississippi punched up at the Supreme Court, noting, “a serious disconnect between the legal and historical communities,” and stating “[t]his Court is not a trained historian. The Justices of the Supreme Court, distinguished as they may be, are not trained historians. We lack both the methodological and substantive knowledge that historians possess.” Likewise, in U.S. v. Holden, the Northern District of Indiana thought that Bruen left him no choice but to invalidate a portion of §922 unconstitutional, while noting “an earnest hope that its author has misunderstood [Bruen].” Even in the case of Bryan Range, a three-judge panel of the Third Circuit unanimously held that dispossessing him of a firearm is constitutional because while “modern-day regulation is not a dead ringer for historical precursors[,] . . . [it] may be analogous enough to pass constitutional muster,” before being overruled 11-4 by an en banc panel.

This brings us to the importance of Range. While the decision purports to do nothing more than to allow Bryan Range, a Pennsylvanian who served a probation sentence in the 1990s for lying to qualify for food stamps, to obtain a firearm, the implications of that decision are enormous. As stated by Judge Schwartz in dissent, “[t]oday, the Majority of our Court has decided that an individual convicted of fraud cannot be barred from possessing a firearm. While my colleagues state that their opinion is narrow, the analytical framework they have applied to reach their conclusion renders most, if not all, felon bans unconstitutional.”

The reason for this is in the details. The majority opinion held that “the Government did not carry its burden to provide a historical analogue to permanently disarm someone like Range, whether grounded in dangerousness or not.” Given that Bruen requires the government to point to a historical analogue to uphold any firearm restriction, the natural (and still open question) is whether a sufficient historical analogue exists for any crime requiring dispossession under §922(g). A close reading of the case would seem to suggest that no historical analogue exists for at least non-violent offenses, but exactly where this line may be drawn has yet to be decided.

According to the United States Sentencing Commission, 7,454 people were convicted of §922(g) offenses in 2021, and 96.9% of those convictions resulted in custodial sentences, many of which were lengthy terms of imprisonment. A great number of the approximately 20,000 – 30,000 people currently serving time in federal prison for §922(g) violations will surely file a writ of habeas corpus to challenge whether their crime of conviction is constitutional. If the answer to that question is no, the likely result is that those people will be released or (in the event of individuals who were convicted of multiple crimes at the same trial, including a §922(g) offense), will receive a new trial. The same is true of individuals serving in state prisons for violations of state analogues to §922(g).

Further, the decision will affect people like Range himself, whose sentences are behind them, but they are nonetheless prohibited from owning or possessing a firearm. While the number of individuals currently serving time for a §922(g) violation is in the tens of thousands, the number of people who have been stripped of their right to possess a firearm as a result of a criminal conviction (or in some instance because of a misdemeanor domestic violence conviction), could reach the low millions. Regardless of one’s personal beliefs on gun ownership, the potential impact of arming a million or more Americans is not negligible.

Ultimately, the Supreme Court will have to decide where the line between constitutional and unconstitutional lies. Justice Kavanaugh, joined by Chief Justice Roberts, seemed to anticipate this issue in their Bruen concurrence when they noted that felony-dispossession is “presumptively lawful.” Therefore, an escape hatch may exist for the Court to outright distinguish Bruen from felony dispossession cases by applying a different analysis. Still another option would be a clear rule that §922(g) is unconstitutional when applied to non-violent offenders, which would likely require finding some historical analogue to support the proposition that a certain indicia of dangerousness warrants dispossession.

Defining the bounds of constitutionality under the current test is no easy task.  As when comparing green hats and green trucks, whether a historical regulation provides a relevant analogue to a present-day law will depend on the specifics of the comparison at hand. In the instance of §922(g), the Range majority decision references crimes as diverse as using profane language on the radio, returning out-of-state bottles or cans to a Michigan recycling center, and library theft of more than $150. It is a difficult to imagine the same historical proxy can be used to define the bounds of those crimes and the innumerable other acts that modern society criminalizes.

Range and Bruen make clear that policy has no place in Second Amendment jurisprudence and that history reigns supreme. While the implication of this line of cases has yet to be fully realized, many longstanding gun laws clearly rest on shaky constitutional ground, particularly those with no clear historical comparator. As we wait for the Supreme Court to clarify the nuances of the Bruen test as applied to a wider-range of gun laws, one thing is clear: legislators looking to regulate guns in a way that withstands constitutional scrutiny would be wise to consult The Pennsylvania Gazette or Poor Richard’s Almanack and not the current headlines.

David Rodkey is the former Managing Editor of JURIST and an Associate Attorney at the Philadelphia-based law firm Dilworth Paxson LLP. His practice areas are wide-ranging and include general commercial law, constitutional law, white-collar defense, and post-conviction relief. He was part of a two-person team that successfully obtained a compassionate release in United States v. Chi Fai Wong, which is believed to be the first case in US history where a federal court granted compassionate release to an individual serving life in prison. 

source


Other Important 2nd Amendment Cases

felons can posses gun cases

Federal Judge Tosses Gun Possession Case Against Convicted Felon United States v. Bullock

Third Circuit Holds that a Nonviolent felon May Not Be Stripped of Second Amendment Rights.

Convicted felons have Second Amendment right to own guns, Louisville judge rules

Ninth Circuit Panel Concludes That Some Felons May Have Second Amendment Rights


RANGE v. ATTORNEY GENERAL UNITED STATES (2022)

United States Court of Appeals, Third Circuit.

Bryan David RANGE, Appellant v. ATTORNEY GENERAL UNITED STATES of America; Regina Lombardo, Acting Director, Bureau of Alcohol, Tobacco, Firearms and Explosives

No. 21-2835

Decided: November 16, 2022

Before: SHWARTZ, KRAUSE and ROTH, Circuit Judges

Michael P. Gottlieb (ARGUED), Vangrossi & Recchuiti, 319 Swede Street, Norristown, PA 19401, Counsel for Appellant Kevin B. Soter (ARGUED), Mark B. Stern, United States Department of Justice, Civil Division, Room 7222, 950 Pennsylvania Avenue, NW, Washington, DC 20530, Counsel for Appellee Joseph G.S. Greenlee (ARGUED), Firearms Policy Coalition Action, 5550 Painted Mirage Road, Suite 320, Las Vegas, NV 89149, Counsel for Amicus Appellant

OPINION

In District of Columbia v. Heller, the Supreme Court held that “the right of the people to keep and bear Arms,” enshrined in the Second Amendment, is an individual right. 554 U.S. 570, 595, 128 S.Ct. 2783, 171 L.Ed.2d 637 (2008). While the precise contours of that individual right are still being defined, the Court has repeatedly stated that it did not question the “longstanding prohibition[ ] on the possession of firearms by felons.” Id. at 626, 128 S.Ct. 2783.

Appellant Bryan Range falls in that category, having pleaded guilty to the felony-equivalent charge of welfare fraud under 62 Pa. Cons. Stat. § 481(a). He now brings an as-applied challenge to 18 U.S.C. § 922(g)(1), contending that his disarmament is inconsistent with the text and history of the Second Amendment and is therefore unconstitutional under New York State Rifle & Pistol Ass’n, Inc. v. Bruen, ––– U.S. ––––, 142 S. Ct. 2111, 213 L.Ed.2d 387 (2022). We disagree. Based on history and tradition, we conclude that “the people” constitutionally entitled to bear arms are the “law-abiding, responsible citizens” of the polity, id. at 2131, a category that properly excludes those who have demonstrated disregard for the rule of law through the commission of felony and felony-equivalent offenses, whether or not those crimes are violent. Additionally, we conclude that even if Range falls within “the people,” the Government has met its burden to demonstrate that its prohibition is consistent with historical tradition. Accordingly, because Range’s felony-equivalent conviction places him outside the class of people traditionally entitled to Second Amendment rights, and because the Government has shown the at-issue prohibition is consistent with historical tradition, we will affirm the District Court’s summary judgment in favor of the Government.

I. Factual and Procedural Background

In 1995, Range pleaded guilty to making false statements about his income to obtain $2,458 of food stamp assistance in violation of 62 Pa. Cons. Stat. § 481(a), a conviction that was then classified as a misdemeanor punishable by up to five years’ imprisonment.1 Range was sentenced to three years’ probation, $2,458 in restitution, $288.29 in costs, and a $100 fine. He has paid the fine, costs, and restitution.

Congress has deemed it “unlawful for any person ․ who has been convicted in any court, of a crime punishable by imprisonment for a term exceeding one year”—the definition of a felony under both federal law, 18 U.S.C. § 3156(a)(3), and traditional legal principles, see Felony, Black’s Law Dictionary (11th ed. 2019)—to “possess in or affecting commerce, any firearm or ammunition.”2 18 U.S.C. § 922(g)(1). In deference to state legislatures, Congress also raised the bar for “any State offense classified by the laws of the State as a misdemeanor” by excluding from the prohibition those misdemeanors “punishable by a term of imprisonment of two years or less.” Id. § 921(a)(20)(B).3 Put differently, it treated state misdemeanors punishable by more than two years’ imprisonment as felony-equivalent offenses. As the maximum punishment for Range’s offense was five years’ imprisonment, his conviction subjected him to § 922(g)(1).

Three years after his conviction, Range attempted to purchase a firearm but was “rejected by the instant background check system.” App. 46, 68, 203. Range’s wife subsequently bought him a deer-hunting rifle, and when that rifle was destroyed in a house fire, she bought him another.4 Sometime in 2010 or 2011, believing his first rejection was an error, Range again attempted to purchase a firearm. Again, he was rejected by the instant background check system. Several years after this rejection, Range “researched the matter” and learned that he was barred from purchasing and possessing firearms because of his welfare fraud conviction. App. 46, 205–06. Having “realize[d] that [he] was not allowed to possess a firearm,” he sold his deer hunting rifle to a firearms dealer. App. 201.

Range has hunted regularly for at least twenty years, most frequently using a bow or a muzzleloader. During the years that he possessed a deer hunting rifle, he routinely hunted with it on the first morning and the two Saturdays of each two-week season. He maintained a Pennsylvania hunting license at the time he filed his lawsuit and averred in deposition testimony that if not barred by § 922(g)(1), he would “for sure” purchase another hunting rifle and “maybe a shotgun” for self-defense in his own home. App. 46, 184, 197, 198, 200–02, 210.

In 2020, Range filed suit in the Eastern District of Pennsylvania, seeking a declaratory judgment that § 922(g) violates the Second Amendment as applied to him, as well as an injunction to bar its enforcement against him. Both Range and the Government moved for summary judgment. The District Court applied the two-step test that this Court adopted in United States v. Marzzarella, 614 F.3d 85 (3d Cir. 2010) and amplified in Binderup v. Attorney General, 836 F.3d 336 (3d Cir. 2016) (en banc), which asks whether (1) a regulation burdens conduct protected by the right to keep and bear arms, and (2) if so, whether that regulation survives means-end scrutiny, id. at 346 (quoting Marzzarella, 614 F.3d at 89). Applying Binderup, the District Court concluded that Range’s challenge failed at step one because the Second Amendment does not protect “unvirtuous citizens,” including any person convicted of “a serious offense,” id. at 349, and Range’s offense qualified as serious under the factors we had identified. The District Court therefore granted the Government’s motion for summary judgment, and this appeal followed.

While Range’s appeal was pending, the Supreme Court issued Bruen, rejecting the means-end component of the second step of Marzzarella and Binderup and holding the first step was “broadly consistent with Heller” to the extent it focused on “the Second Amendment’s text, as informed by history.” 142 S. Ct. at 2127. The Government filed a letter pursuant to Federal Rule of Appellate Procedure 28(j), contending that Range’s Second Amendment challenge still must fail under Bruen’s framework. Range responded with his own Rule 28(j) letter, underscoring Bruen’s emphasis on history and asserting “there is no history in 1791 that given the facts of Mr. Range’s case that he would be disarmed and prevented from owning and possessing firearms.” Dkt. No. 41 at 2. The panel ordered supplemental briefing on (1) Bruen’s impact, if any, on the multifactor analysis developed in Binderup and Holloway v. Attorney General, 948 F.3d 164 (3d Cir. 2020); (2) whether Bruen shifts the burden to the Government to prove that the challenger is outside the scope of those entitled to Second Amendment rights, and whether the Government has met that burden here; and (3) whether we should remand this matter to the District Court.5

In supplemental briefing on the effect of Bruen, Range argues that the history and tradition of the Second Amendment demonstrates that only individuals with a dangerous propensity for violence, as opposed to peaceful citizens like him, can be disarmed. Amici filed a brief on Range’s behalf, echoing his contention that “[t]he historical tradition of disarming dangerous persons provides no justification for disarming Range.” Amicus Br. 26. The Government urges us to reject a narrow focus on dangerousness, reaffirm our holdings in Binderup and subsequent cases that the Second Amendment extends only to people considered “virtuous citizens,” and therefore hold that there is a longstanding tradition of disarming citizens who are not law-abiding.

With the benefit of Bruen, cases applying Bruen,6 and the parties’ briefing and arguments, we turn to the merits of Range’s appeal.

II. Jurisdiction and Standard of Review

The District Court had jurisdiction under 28 U.S.C. § 1331. We have appellate jurisdiction under 28 U.S.C. § 1291. We review the District Court’s order granting summary judgment de novo, see Mylan Inc. v. SmithKline Beecham Corp., 723 F.3d 413, 418 (3d Cir. 2013), viewing the facts and making all reasonable inferences in the non-movant’s favor, see Hugh v. Butler Cty. Family YMCA, 418 F.3d 265, 266–67 (3d Cir. 2005). Summary judgment is appropriate where “there is no genuine dispute as to any material fact and the movant is entitled to judgment as a matter of law.” Fed. R. Civ. P. 56(a). The moving party is entitled to judgment as a matter of law when the non-moving party fails to make “a sufficient showing on an essential element of her case with respect to which she has the burden of proof.”7 See Celotex Corp. v. Catrett, 477 U.S. 317, 323, 106 S.Ct. 2548, 91 L.Ed.2d 265 (1986).

III. Bruen’s Doctrinal Impact

Applying Bruen’s historical focus, we conclude § 922(g)(1) comports with legislatures’ longstanding authority and discretion to disarm citizens unwilling to obey the government and its laws, whether or not they had demonstrated a propensity for violence. We proceed in two parts. We begin by explaining how the Supreme Court replaced our two-step framework with a distinct test focused on the text and history of the Second Amendment. Next, we examine disarmament laws from the seventeenth to the nineteenth centuries to determine whether Range’s disarmament fits within the nation’s history and tradition of the right to keep and bear arms.

A. Post-Bruen Standard for Second Amendment Challenges

The Supreme Court’s decision in Bruen modifies our prior test for analyzing Second Amendment challenges to 18 U.S.C. § 922(g)(1).

Before Bruen, we analyzed Second Amendment challenges under a two-part test that was eventually adopted by most of our sister Circuits. Marzzarella, 614 F.3d at 89; see also Binderup, 836 F.3d at 346 (“Nearly every court of appeals has cited Marzzarella favorably.”). At the first step, we considered whether the challenged law burdened conduct within the scope of the Second Amendment. Marzzarella, 614 F.3d at 89. In examining this subject, we observed that “the right to bear arms was tied to the concept of a virtuous citizenry and that accordingly, the government could disarm ‘unvirtuous citizens[,]” including “any person who has committed a serious criminal offense, violent or nonviolent.”8 Binderup, 836 F.3d at 348 (quoting United States v. Yancey, 621 F.3d 681, 684–85 (7th Cir. 2010)); see also Heller, 554 U.S. at 626–27 & n.26, 128 S.Ct. 2783. If the first step was met, we proceeded to the second step and assessed whether the regulation withstood means-end scrutiny. Marzzarella, 614 F.3d at 89.

Bruen, however, abrogated Binderup’s two-step inquiry and directed the federal courts, in a single step, to look to the Second Amendment’s text and “the Nation’s historical tradition of firearm regulation.” 142 S. Ct. at 2126, 2130; see also Frein v. Pa. State Police, 47 F.4th 247, 254, 256 (3d Cir. 2022) (recognizing Bruen abrogated our two-step framework).9 “Only if a firearm regulation is consistent with this Nation’s historical tradition may a court conclude that the individual’s conduct falls outside the Second Amendment’s ‘unqualified command.’ ” Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2126 (quoting Konigsberg v. State Bar of Cal., 366 U.S. 36, 50 n.10, 81 S.Ct. 997, 6 L.Ed.2d 105 (1961)). Additionally, because “the Constitution presumptively protects [individual] conduct” covered by “the Second Amendment’s plain text,” the Court explained, the government has the burden of justifying its regulation of that conduct by demonstrating “not simply [ ] that the regulation promotes an important interest,” but that “the regulation is consistent with this Nation’s historical tradition of firearm regulation.” Id.10

Under Bruen, the question is whether the regulation at issue is “relevantly similar” to regulations at the Founding. Id. at 2132 (quoting Cass R. Sunstein, On Analogical Reasoning, 106 Harv. L. Rev. 741, 773 (1993)). To make that determination, we must employ “analogical reasoning” and compare “how and why the regulations burden a law-abiding citizen’s right to armed self-defense.” Id. at 2132–33. Specifically, the government must “identify a well-established and representative historical analogue, not a historical twin.” Id. at 2133. “So even if a modern-day regulation is not a dead ringer for historical precursors, it still may be analogous enough to pass constitutional muster.” Id.

Bruen does not preclude our review of Range’s appeal on the record before us. Bruen did not address the substantive issues that we must now determine. Unlike the open-carry licensing regime in Bruen that created a conduct-based constraint on public carry, § 922(g)(1) imposes a status-based restriction—namely, a possession ban on those convicted of crimes punishable by more than one year in prison or by more than two years in prison in the case of state law misdemeanors. See Eugene Volokh, Implementing the Right to Keep and Bear Arms for Self-Defense: An Analytical Framework and a Research Agenda, 56 UCLA L. Rev. 1443, 1443 (2009) (distinguishing between “what,” “who,” “where,” “how,” and “when” firearm restrictions). Despite that difference, Bruen still requires us to assess whether the Government has demonstrated through relevant historical analogues that § 922(g)(1) “is consistent with this Nation’s historical tradition of firearm regulation.” 142 S. Ct. at 2134. As set forth below, the historical record shows that legislatures had broad discretion to prohibit those who did not respect the law from having firearms. Our assessment confirms that individuals like Range, who commit felonies and felony-equivalent offenses, are not part of “the people” whom the Second Amendment protects. Therefore, § 922(g)(1) as applied to Range is constitutional under the Second Amendment.

B. Scope of Second Amendment Rights in Historical Perspective

As instructed by Bruen, we begin our analysis with the text of the Second Amendment, which protects “the right of the people to keep and bear Arms,” U.S. Const. amend. II, and consider if Range, as a felon equivalent under 18 U.S.C. § 921(a)(20)(B), is among those protected by the Amendment. Cf. Binderup, 836 F.3d at 357 (Hardiman, J., concurring in part) (“[T]he Founders understood that not everyone possessed Second Amendment rights. These appeals require us to decide who count among ‘the people’ entitled to keep and bear arms.”); United States v. Quiroz, No. 22-CR-00104, ––– F.Supp.3d ––––, ––––, 2022 WL 4352482, at *10 (W.D. Tex. Sept. 19, 2022) (explaining “this Nation does have a historical tradition of excluding specific groups from the rights and powers reserved to ‘the people’ ”).

The language of Bruen provides three insights into pertinent limits on “the people” whom the Second Amendment protects. First, the majority characterized the holders of Second Amendment rights as “law-abiding” citizens no fewer than fourteen times. Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2122, 2125, 2131, 2133–34, 2135 n.8, 2138 & n.9, 2150, 2156; accord Heller, 554 U.S. at 625, 635, 128 S.Ct. 2783. These included its holding that the New York statute “violates the Fourteenth Amendment in that it prevents law-abiding citizens with ordinary self-defense needs from exercising their right to keep and bear arms,” Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2156, its explanation that the Second Amendment “ ‘elevates above all other interests the right of law-abiding, responsible citizens to use arms’ for self-defense,” id. at 2131 (quoting Heller, 554 U.S. at 635, 128 S.Ct. 2783), and its instruction to identify historical analogues to modern firearm regulations by assessing “how and why the regulations burden a law-abiding citizen’s right to armed self-defense,” id. at 2133.11 The Court also quoted nineteenth-century sources extending the right to keep and bear arms to “all loyal and well-disposed inhabitants,” and disarming any person who made “an improper or dangerous use of weapons.” Id. at 2152 (emphasis added) (quoting Cong. Globe, 39th Cong., 1st Sess., at 908–909; and Circular No. 5, Freedmen’s Bureau, Dec. 22, 1865).

Second, the Court clarified that, despite the infirmity of New York’s discretionary may-issue permitting regime, “nothing in our analysis should be interpreted to suggest the unconstitutionality of the 43 States’ ‘shall-issue’ licensing regimes ․ [,] which often require applicants to undergo a [criminal] background check” and “are designed to ensure only that those bearing arms in the jurisdiction are, in fact ‘law-abiding, responsible citizens.’ ” Id. at 2138 n.9 (quoting Heller, 554 U.S. at 635, 128 S.Ct. 2783). These criminal background checks that the Court indicated are constitutional are not limited to violent offenses; shall-issue statutes typically disqualify any person “prohibited from possessing a firearm under federal law.” Wash. Rev. Code Ann. § 9.41.070(1)(a) (2021); accord Colo. Rev. Stat. Ann. § 18-12-203(1)(c) (2021); Kan. Stat. Ann. § 75-7c04(a)(2) (2021); Miss. Code. Ann. § 45-9-101(2)(d) (2022); N.H. Rev. Stat. Ann. § 159:6(I)(a) (2021); N.C. Gen. Stat. Ann. § 14-415.12(b)(1) (2022).

Third, neither Bruen nor either of the Court’s earlier explanations of the individual right to keep and bear arms casts doubt on § 922(g)(1). To the contrary, Justice Scalia’s majority opinion in Heller twice described “prohibitions on the possession of firearms by felons” as both “longstanding” and “presumptively lawful[.]” 554 U.S. at 626–27 & n.26, 128 S.Ct. 2783.12 Writing for the McDonald plurality, Justice Alito “repeat[ed] those assurances.” 561 U.S. at 786, 130 S.Ct. 3020. In Bruen, Justice Thomas’s majority opinion acknowledged that the right to keep and bear arms is “subject to certain reasonable, well-defined restrictions,” Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2156 (citing Heller, 554 U.S. at 581, 128 S.Ct. 2783), and the concurrences by Justices Alito and Kavanaugh, the latter joined by the Chief Justice, echoed the Court’s assertions in Heller and McDonald. Id. at 2162 (Kavanaugh, J., concurring) (quoting Heller, 554 U.S. at 626–27 & n.26, 128 S.Ct. 2783); id. at 2157 (Alito, J., concurring); see also United States v. Coombes, No. 22-CR-00189, ––– F.Supp.3d ––––, ––––, 2022 WL 4367056, at *9 (N.D. Okla. Sept. 21, 2022) (“[T]he Bruen majority did not abrogate its prior statements in Heller and McDonald.”).

Thus, although the Supreme Court has not provided an “exhaustive historical analysis ․ of the full scope of the Second Amendment,” Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2128; Heller, 554 U.S. at 626, 128 S.Ct. 2783, Heller, McDonald, and Bruen provide a window into the Court’s view of the status-based disarmament of criminals: that this group falls outside “the people”—whether or not their crimes involved violence—and that § 922(g)(1) is well-rooted in the nation’s history and tradition of firearm regulation.13

Our Court’s own review of the historical record supports the Supreme Court’s understanding: Those whose criminal records evince disrespect for the law are outside the community of law-abiding citizens entitled to keep and bear arms.14 Our previous decisions, endorsed by several sister courts of appeals, have expressed a related view in terms of the theory of “civic virtue.”15 See, e.g., Folajtar v. Att’y Gen., 980 F.3d 897, 902 (3d Cir. 2020); Binderup, 836 F.3d at 348; United States v. Carpio-Leon, 701 F.3d 974, 979–80 (4th Cir. 2012); United States v. Yancey, 621 F.3d 681, 684–85 (7th Cir. 2010); United States v. Vongxay, 594 F.3d 1111, 1118 (9th Cir. 2010). Moreover, as detailed below, the pertinent historical periods were replete with laws “relevantly similar” to the modern prohibition on felon firearm possession because they categorically disqualified people from possessing firearms based on a judgment that certain individuals were untrustworthy parties to the nation’s social compact.16

The Bruen Court warned that “not all history is created equal” and catalogued the sources that are most probative of the right’s original meaning. 142 S. Ct. at 2136. Emphasizing that the right codified in the Second Amendment was a “pre-existing right,” the Court saw particular relevance in “English history dating from the late 1600s, along with American colonial views leading up to the founding.” Id. at 2127 (citing Heller, 554 U.S. at 595, 128 S.Ct. 2783).17 The Court made this same point in Heller. 554 U.S. at 592, 128 S.Ct. 2783. The Bruen Court also found highly relevant post-ratification practices from the late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries. See Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2136. In contrast, although the Court considered history from Reconstruction to the late nineteenth century, it underscored that it did so merely to confirm its conclusions and that evidence from this period is less informative. See id. at 2137.

1. England’s Restoration and Glorious Revolution

We begin with the late seventeenth century, when the English government repeatedly disarmed individuals whose conduct indicated a disrespect for the sovereign and its dictates. Also, the advent of the English Bill of Rights during this period confirmed Parliament’s authority to delineate which members of the community could “have arms ․ by Law.” 1 W. & M., Sess. 2, ch. 2, § 7 (Eng. 1689).

In the contentious period following the English Civil War, the restored Stuart monarchs disarmed nonconformist (i.e., non-Anglican) Protestants. See Joyce Lee Malcolm, To Keep and Bear Arms: The Origins of an Anglo-American Right 45 (1994) (describing how Charles II “totally disarmed ․ religious dissenters”); Amicus Br. 6 (“Leading up to the Glorious Revolution of 1688, ․ nonAnglican [sic] Protestants were often disarmed.”). The reason the Crown seized nonconformists’ weapons, according to Amici, is that non-Anglican Protestants were dangerous. But the notion that every disarmed nonconformist was dangerous defies common sense. Moreover, Amici’s resort to dangerousness as the sole explanation for this measure ignores Anglicans’ well-documented concern that nonconformists would not obey the King and abide by the law.

By definition, nonconformists refused to participate in the Church of England, an institution headed by the King as a matter of English law. See Church of England, BBC (June 30, 2011), https://www.bbc.co.uk/religion/religions/christianity/cofe/cofe_1.shtml (describing “the Act of Supremacy” enacted during the reign of Henry VIII). Indeed, many refused to take mandatory oaths recognizing the King’s sovereign authority over matters of religion. See Frederick B. Jonassen, “So Help Me?”: Religious Expression and Artifacts in the Oath of Office and the Courtroom Oath, 12 Cardozo Pub. L., Pol’y & Ethics J. 303, 322 (2014) (describing Charles II’s reinstation of the Oath of Supremacy); Caroline Robbins, Selden’s Pills: State Oaths in England, 1558–1714, 35 Huntington Lib. Q. 303, 314–15 (1972) (discussing nonconformists’ refusal to take such oaths). Anglicans, in turn, accused nonconformists of believing that their faith exempted them from obedience to the law. See Christopher Haigh, ‘Theological Wars’: ‘Socinians’ v. ‘Antinomians’ in Restoration England, 67 J. Ecclesiastical Hist. 325, 326, 334 (2016). In short, the historical record suggests nonconformists as a group were disarmed because their religious status was viewed as a proxy for disobedience to the Crown’s sovereign authority and disrespect for the law, placing them outside the civic community of law-abiding citizens.

Even when Protestants’ right to keep arms was restored, it was expressly made subject to the discretion of Parliament. One year after the Glorious Revolution of 1688 replaced the Catholic King James II with William of Orange and Mary, James’s Protestant daughter, see Alice Ristroph, The Second Amendment in a Carceral State, 116 Nw. U. L. Rev. 203, 228 (2021), Parliament enacted the English Bill of Rights, which declared: “Subjects which are Protestants, may have Arms for their Defence suitable to their Conditions, and as allowed by Law,” 1 W. & M., Sess. 2, ch. 2, § 7 (Eng. 1689) (emphasis added). Thus, this declaration, which the Supreme Court has described as the “predecessor to our Second Amendment,” Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2141 (quoting Heller, 554 U.S. at 593, 128 S.Ct. 2783), reveals the “historical understanding,” id. at 2131, that the legislature—Parliament—had the power and discretion to determine who was sufficiently loyal and law-abiding to exercise the right to bear arms. Cf. Lois G. Schwoerer, To Hold and Bear Arms: The English Perspective, 76 Chi.-Kent L. Rev. 27, 47–48 (2000) (explaining how the English Bill of Rights preserved Parliament’s authority to limit who could bear arms).

In 1689, Parliament enacted a status-based restriction forbidding Catholics who refused to take an oath renouncing their faith from owning firearms, except as necessary for self-defense. An Act for the Better Securing the Government by Disarming Papists and Reputed Papists, 1 W. & M., Sess. 1, ch. 15 (Eng. 1688); see Malcolm, supra, at 123. Proponents of the view that disarmament depended exclusively on dangerousness have argued that Catholics categorically posed a threat of violence at this time. See Kanter v. Barr, 919 F.3d 437, 457 (7th Cir. 2019) (Barrett, J., dissenting); C. Kevin Marshall, Why Can’t Martha Stewart Have a Gun?, 32 Harv. J.L. & Pub. Pol’y 695, 723 (2009). Again, however, this interpretation not only rests on the implausible premise that all Catholics were violent, but also ignores the more likely historical reason for disarming this entire group: their perceived disrespect for and disobedience to the Crown and English law. That is manifest in the statute’s oath requirement. When individuals swore that they rejected the tenets of Catholicism, their right to own weapons was restored. An Act for the Better Securing the Government by Disarming Papists and Reputed Papists, 1 W. & M., Sess. 1, ch. 15 (Eng. 1688).

Disavowal of religious tenets hardly demonstrated that the swearing individual no longer had the capacity to commit violence; rather, the oath was a gesture of allegiance to the English government and an assurance of conformity to its laws. Likewise, contemporaneous arguments against tolerating Catholicism contended that Catholics’ faith subverted the rule of law by placing the dictates of a “foreign power,” i.e., the Pope, before English legal commands. See Diego Lucci, John Locke on Atheism, Catholicism, Antinomianism, and Deism, 20 Etica & Politica/Ethics & Pol. 201, 228–29 (2018). The disarmament of Catholics in 1689 thus provides another example of the seizure of weapons from individuals whose status demonstrated, not a proclivity for violence, but rather a disregard for the legally binding decrees of the sovereign.

2. Colonial America

The earliest firearm legislation in colonial America prohibited Native Americans, Black people, and indentured servants from owning firearms.18 See Michael A. Bellesiles, Gun Laws in Early America: The Regulation of Firearms Ownership, 1607–1794, 16 Law & Hist. Rev. 567, 578–79 (1998). Amici contend that these restrictions affected individuals outside the political community and so cannot serve as analogues to contemporary restraints on citizens like Range. Amicus Br. 30–31; see also Carpio-Leon, 701 F.3d at 978 n.1 (concluding such individuals may not have been part of “the people” at the Founding). But even accepting Amici’s argument, colonial history furnishes numerous examples in which full-fledged members of the political community as it then existed—i.e., free, Christian, white men—were disarmed due to conduct evincing inadequate faithfulness to the sovereign and its laws.

During the late 1630s, for example, an outspoken preacher in Boston named Anne Hutchinson challenged the Massachusetts Bay government’s authority over spiritual matters and instead advocated personal relationships with the divine. See Edmund S. Morgan, The Case Against Anne Hutchinson, 10 New Eng. Q. 635, 637–38, 644 (1937). Governor John Winthrop accused Hutchinson and her followers of being Antinomians, those who viewed their salvation as exempting them from the law, and banished her. Id. at 648; Ann Fairfax Withington & Jack Schwartz, The Political Trial of Anne Hutchinson, 51 New Eng. Q. 226, 226 (1978). The colonial government also disarmed at least fifty-eight of Hutchinson’s supporters, not because those supporters had demonstrated a propensity for violence, but “to embarrass the offenders,” as they were forced to personally deliver their arms to the authorities in an act of public submission. James F. Cooper, Jr., Anne Hutchinson and the “Lay Rebellion” Against the Clergy, 61 New Eng. Q. 381, 391 (1988). Disarming Hutchinson’s supporters, in other words, served to shame colonists whose disavowal of the rule of law placed them outside the Puritan’s civic community and obedience to the commands of the government. Cf. John Felipe Acevedo, Dignity Takings in the Criminal Law of Seventeenth-Century England and the Massachusetts Bay Colony, 92 Chi.-Kent L. Rev. 743, 761 (2017) (describing other shaming punishments used at the time, including scarlet letters).

Likewise, Catholics in the American colonies (as in Britain) were subject to disarmament without demonstrating a proclivity for violence. It is telling that, notwithstanding Maryland’s genesis as a haven for persecuted English Catholics, see Michael W. McConnell, The Origins and Historical Understanding of Free Exercise of Religion, 103 Harv. L. Rev. 1409, 1424 (1990), Maryland—as well as Virginia and Pennsylvania—confiscated firearms from their Catholic residents during the Seven Years’ War, see Bellesiles, supra, at 574; Joseph G.S. Greenlee, The Historical Justification for Prohibiting Dangerous Persons from Possessing Arms, 20 Wyo. L. Rev. 249, 263 (2020). That decision was not in response to violence; to the contrary, Catholics had remained peaceable even when the colony’s Anglican Protestants took control of its government and required Catholics to take oaths recognizing the legal authority of the Crown, rather than the Pope, over matters of religion. See Michael Graham, S.J., Popish Plots: Protestant Fears in Early Colonial Maryland, 1676–1689, 79 Cath. Hist. Rev. 197, 197 (1993) (“[L]ittle sustained opposition to [the Anglican leadership] crystallized within the colony. What the Protestant Associators had done ․ was widely accepted.”); Denis M. Moran, Anti-Catholicism in Early Maryland Politics: The Protestant Revolution, 61 Am. Cath. Hist. Soc’y 213, 235 (1950) (explaining how the oaths “asserted the king’s supremacy in spiritual as well as in temporal matters”). In sum, Protestants in the colonies—as in England—disarmed Catholics not because they uniformly posed a threat of armed resistance, but rather because the Protestant majorities in those colonies viewed Catholics as defying sovereign authority and communal values.

3. Revolutionary War

Revolutionary-era history furnishes other examples of legislatures disarming non-violent individuals because their actions evinced an unwillingness to comply with the legal norms of the nascent social compact.19

John Locke—whose views profoundly influenced the American revolutionaries 20 —argued that the replacement of individual judgments of what behavior is transgressive with communal norms is an essential characteristic of the social contract. See John Locke, Two Treatises of Government § 163 (Thomas I. Cook, ed., Hafner Press 1947) (reasoning “there only is political society where every one of the members hath quitted his natural power [to judge transgressions and] resigned it up into the hands of the community”). Members of a social compact, he explained, have a civic obligation to comply with communal judgments regarding proper behavior.21

In the newly proclaimed states, compliance with that civic obligation translated to entitlement to keep and bear arms, with many of the newly independent states enacting statutes that required individuals, as a condition of keeping their arms, to commit to the incipient social compact by swearing fidelity to the revolutionary regime.22 See Robert H. Churchill, Gun Regulation, the Police Power, and the Right to Keep Arms in Early America: The Legal Context of the Second Amendment, 25 Law & Hist. Rev. 139, 158 (2007).

In Connecticut, for example, as hostilities with Britain worsened, colonists denounced loyalists’ dereliction of their duties to the civic community. The people of Coventry passed a resolution in 1774 stating loyalists were “unworthy of that friendship and esteem which constitutes the bond of social happiness, and ought to be treated with contempt and total neglect.” G.A. Gilbert, The Connecticut Loyalists, 4 Am. Hist. Rev. 273, 280 (1899) (describing this resolution as “a fair sample of most of the others passed at this time”). “Committees of Inspection” publicized the names and addresses of suspected loyalists in local newspapers, describing them as “persons held up to public view as enemies to their country,” id. at 280–81, and in 1775, this stigmatization of individuals suspected of infidelity to the inchoate United States culminated in a statute prohibiting anyone who defamed resolutions of the Continental Congress from keeping arms, voting, or serving as a civil official, see id. at 282.

Pennsylvania likewise disarmed non-violent individuals who were unwilling to abide by the newly sovereign state’s legal norms. The legislature enacted a statute in 1777 requiring all white male inhabitants above the age of eighteen to swear to “be faithful and bear true allegiance to the commonwealth of Pennsylvania as a free and independent state,” Act of June 13, 1777, § 1 (1777), 9 The Statutes at Large of Pennsylvania from 1652–1801 110, 111 (William Stanley Ray ed., 1903), and providing that those who failed to take the oath—without regard to dangerousness or propensity for physical violence—“shall be disarmed” by the local authorities, id. at 112–13, § 3.

This statute is particularly instructive because Pennsylvania’s 1776 state constitution protected the people’s right to bear arms. See Cornell, Don’t Know Much About History, supra, at 670–71; Marshall, supra, at 724. Yet Pennsylvania’s loyalty oath law deprived sizable numbers of pacifists of that right because oath-taking violated the religious convictions of Quakers, Mennonites, Moravians, and other groups. Jim Wedeking, Quaker State: Pennsylvania’s Guide to Reducing the Friction for Religious Outsiders Under the Establishment Clause, 2 N.Y.U. J.L. & Liberty 28, 51 (2006); see also Thomas C. McHugh, Moravian Opposition to the Pennsylvania Test Acts, 1777 to 1789, at 49–50 (Sept. 7, 1965) (M.A. thesis, Lehigh University) (on file with the Leigh Preserve Institutional Repository). So while Amici contend that individuals disarmed under loyalty oath statutes “posed a grave danger and were often violent,” Amicus Br. 12, Pennsylvania’s disarmament of this sizable portion of the state’s populace cannot be explained on that ground. See Heller, 554 U.S. at 590, 128 S.Ct. 2783 (“Quakers opposed the use of arms not just for militia service, but for any violent purpose whatsoever․”); cf. Folajtar, 980 F.3d at 908 n.11 (explaining “[r]efusing to swear an oath” does not “qualify as dangerous”).

Instead, the Pennsylvania legislature forbade Quakers and other religious minorities from keeping arms because their refusal to swear allegiance demonstrated that they would not submit to communal judgments embodied in law when it conflicted with personal conviction. See Wedeking, supra, at 51–52 (describing how Quakers were “penal[ized] for allegiance to their religious scruples over the new government”). The act, in other words, was “an effort by Pennsylvania’s Constitutionalist party to restrictively define citizenship”—i.e., what eventually became “the people”—“to those capable of displaying the requisite virtue.” Cornell, Don’t Know Much About History, supra, at 671.

Exercising its broad authority to disarm individuals who disrespected the rule of law, Virginia’s General Assembly also passed a loyalty oath statute in 1777. An Act to Oblige the Free Male Inhabitants of this State Above a Certain Age to Give Assurance of Allegiances to the Same, and for Other Purposes ch. III (1777), 9 Statutes at Large; Being a Collection of All the Laws of Virginia, from the First Session of the Legislature in the Year 1619 281, 281 (William W. Hening ed., 1821). That law disarmed “all free born male inhabitants of this state, above the age of sixteen years, except imported servants during the time of their service” who refused to swear their “allegiance and fidelity” to the state. Id. But these individuals could not have been considered dangerous spies or threats of violence: the statute still required disarmed individuals to attend militia trainings and run drills without weapons, id. at 282—an indignity previously inflicted upon free Black men, Churchill, supra, at 160. Instead, this use of disarmament as a method of public humiliation reveals the statute’s true social function: distinguishing those unwilling to follow the dictates of the new government from law-abiding members of the civic community.

In sum, the “how and why,” Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2133, of these oath statutes’ burden on the right to bear arms teaches us two things about the historical understanding of status-based prohibitions. First, in keeping with Locke’s view that compliance with communal judgment is an inextricable feature of political society, these laws “defined membership of the body politic” by disarming individuals whose refusal to take these oaths evinced not necessarily a propensity for violence, but rather a disrespect for the rule of law and the norms of the civic community. Churchill, supra, at 158. Second, legislatures were understood to have the authority and broad discretion to decide when disobedience with the law was sufficiently grave to exclude even a non-violent offender from the people entitled to keep and bear arms. Cf. Dru Stevenson, In Defense of Felon-in-Possession Laws, 43 Cardozo L. Rev. 1573, 1586 (2022) (“[T]he founders thought the legislature should decide which groups pose a threat to the social order or the community.”).

4. Ratification Debates

The ensuing deliberations over whether to ratify the Constitution similarly illustrate the Founding generation’s understanding of legislatures’ power and discretion over disarmament of those not considered law-abiding.

In Pennsylvania, debates between the Federalists and Anti-Federalists “were among the most influential and widely distributed of any essays published during ratification.” Saul Cornell, Commonplace or Anachronism: The Standard Model, the Second Amendment, and the Problem of History in Contemporary Constitutional Theory, 16 Const. Comment. 221, 227 (1999). Those essays included “The Dissent of the Minority,” which was published by the state’s Anti-Federalist delegates, id. at 232–33, and which the Supreme Court has viewed as “highly influential” to the adoption of the Second Amendment, Heller, 554 U.S. at 604, 128 S.Ct. 2783. The amendment proposed by the Dissent of the Minority stated:

[T]he people have a right to bear arms for the defence of themselves and their own State or the United States, or for the purpose of killing game; and no law shall be passed for disarming the people or any of them unless for crimes committed, or real danger of public injury from individuals.

2 Bernard Schwartz, The Bill of Rights: A Documentary History 665 (1971) (emphasis added).

As the Dissent of the Minority’s proposal makes clear, members of the Founding generation viewed “[c]rimes committed—violent or not—[as] ․ an independent ground for exclusion from the right to keep and bear arms.” Binderup, 836 F.3d at 349 (quotation omitted); see also Folajtar, 980 F.3d at 908–09. Amici insist that the proposal’s crime and danger clauses must be read together as authorizing the disarmament of dangerous criminals only. See Amicus Br. 16; see also Greenlee, supra at 267; Binderup, 836 F.3d at 367 (Hardiman, J., concurring in part). But the Dissent of the Minority’s use of the disjunctive “or” refutes this counterargument: The dissenters distinguished between criminal convictions and dangerousness, and provided that either could support disarmament. See, e.g., United States v. Woods, 571 U.S. 31, 45–46, 134 S.Ct. 557, 187 L.Ed.2d 472 (2013) (explaining the “ordinary use” of “or” “is almost always disjunctive”—i.e., “the words that it connects are to ‘be given separate meanings’ ”) (quoting Reiter v. Sonotone Corp., 442 U.S. 330, 339, 99 S.Ct. 2326, 60 L.Ed.2d 931 (1979)).

The Dissent of the Minority therefore comports with the longstanding tradition in English and American law of disarming even non-violent individuals whose actions demonstrated a disrespect for the rule of law as embodied in the sovereign’s binding norms.

5. Other Non-Violent Offenses

Punishments meted out for a variety of non-violent offenses between the seventeenth and nineteenth centuries provide additional support for legislatures’ authority to disarm even non-violent offenders.

Historically, several non-violent felonies were punishable by death and forfeiture of the perpetrator’s entire estate. See Folajtar, 980 F.3d at 904–05. As the Government observes, those offenses included larceny, repeated forgery, and false pretenses—all of which involve deceit or the wrongful deprivation of another’s property and closely resemble Range’s welfare fraud offense. Appellees’ Supp. Br. 7–8.23 A fortiori, given the draconian punishments that traditionally could be imposed for these types of non-violent felonies, the comparatively lenient consequence of disarmament under 18 U.S.C. § 922(g)(1) is permissible.24

Additionally, legislatures in the American colonies and United States authorized the seizure of firearms from individuals who committed non-violent, misdemeanor hunting offenses.25 In 1652, New Netherlands passed an ordinance that forbid “firing within the jurisdiction of this city [of New Amsterdam] or about the Fort, with any guns at Partridges or other Game that may by chance fly within the city, on pain of forfeiting the Gun ․” 1652 N.Y. Laws 138. A 1745 North Carolina law prohibited nonresidents from hunting deer in “the King’s Wast” and stated that any violator “shall forfeit his gun” to the authorities. Act of Apr. 20, ch. III (1745), 23 Acts of the North Carolina General Assembly 218, 219 (1805). New Jersey enacted a statute “for the preservation of deer, and other game” in 1771 that punished non-residents caught trespassing with a firearm by seizing the individuals’ guns. 1771 N.J. Laws 19–20.

State legislatures continued to enact such laws after the Revolution. To protect the sheep of Naushon Island, Massachusetts passed a statute requiring armed trespassers on the island to forfeit their guns.26 An Act for the Protection and Security of the Sheep and Other Stock on Tarpaulin Cove Island, Otherwise Called Naushon Island, and on Nennemessett Island, and Several Small Islands Contiguous, Situated in the County of Dukes County § 2 (1790), 1 Private and Special Statutes of the Commonwealth of Massachusetts 258, 259 (Manning & Loring ed., 1805). Virginia and Maryland punished individuals who hunted wild fowl on rivers at night by seizing their guns. 1832 Va. Acts 70; 1838 Md. Laws 291–92. And Delaware law required non-residents who hunted wild geese on the state’s waterways to forfeit their guns, even though the statute specified that this hunting offense was a misdemeanor. 12 Del. Laws 365 (1863).

As these centuries of hunting statutes show, legislatures repeatedly exercised their authority to decide when non-violent offenses were sufficiently grave transgressions to justify limiting violators’ ability to keep and bear arms.27

* * * * *

We draw three critical lessons from the historical record examined above. First, legislatures traditionally used status-based restrictions to disqualify categories of persons from possessing firearms. Second, they did so not merely based on an individual’s demonstrated propensity for violence, but rather to address the threat purportedly posed by entire categories of people to an orderly society and compliance with its legal norms. Third, legislatures had, as a matter of separated powers, both authority and broad discretion to determine when individuals’ status or conduct evinced such a threat sufficient to warrant disarmament.28

IV. Range’s Claims

Having identified the appropriate test and reviewed the historical evidence in this area, we now turn to Range’s claims.

Range committed an offense that Pennsylvania has classified as a misdemeanor punishable by more than two years’ imprisonment, 62 Pa. Cons. Stat. § 481(a), and Congress has concluded is sufficiently serious to exclude Range from the body of law-abiding, responsible citizens entitled to keep and bear arms, see 18 U.S.C. §§ 921(a)(20)(B), 922(g)(1).29 That determination fits comfortably within the longstanding tradition of legislation disarming individuals whose actions evince a disrespect for the rule of law. Interpreting the text of the Second Amendment in light of the right’s “historical background,” Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2127 (quoting Heller, 554 U.S. at 592, 128 S.Ct. 2783), we conclude that Range’s criminal conviction placed him beyond the ambit of “the people” protected by the Second Amendment.

Range asserts that “[t]he Government has failed to meet its burden of proving that the plaintiff’s conviction places him outside the scope of those entitled to Second Amendment rights based on the historical analysis of those who can be disarmed.”30 Appellant’s Supp. Br. 1. Notwithstanding the historical evidence surveyed above, Range contends that his disarmament is inconsistent with the nation’s tradition of firearm regulation “because he is not dangerous.” Opening Br. 28. Echoing positions expressed by some judges, Amici agree, arguing “English and American tradition support firearm prohibitions on dangerous persons” but “[t]here is no tradition of disarming peaceable citizens.” Amicus Br. 2; see Folajtar, 980 F.3d at 912 (Bibas, J., dissenting); Kanter, 919 F.3d at 451 (Barrett, J., dissenting); Binderup, 836 F.3d at 369 (Hardiman, J., concurring in part). Our review of the historical record convinces us otherwise. Non-violent individuals were repeatedly disarmed between the seventeenth and nineteenth centuries because legislatures determined that those individuals lacked respect for the rule of law and thus fell outside the community of law-abiding citizens. That longstanding tradition refutes Range’s constrictive account of Anglo-American history as prohibiting the government from disarming non-violent individuals.

Amici offer a few statutes that purportedly prove legislatures’ inability to disarm non-violent offenders, but these laws confirm our view. Specifically, Amici cite a 1785 Massachusetts law that forbid tax collectors and sheriffs from embezzling tax revenue. Amicus Br. 32 (citing 1785 Mass. Laws 516).31 Although the statute permitted estate sales to recover embezzled funds, “the necessities of life—including firearms—could not be sold.” Id. Likewise, Amici discuss a 1650 Connecticut law exempting weapons from execution in civil actions and four statutes providing similar protections for militia arms. Id. at 33 (citing The Public Records of the Colony of Connecticut, Prior to the Union with New Haven Colony, May 1665, at 537 (J. Hammond Trumbull ed., 1850); 1 Stat. 271, § 1 (1792); Archives of Maryland Proceedings and Acts of the General Assembly of Maryland, at 557 (William Hand Browne ed., 1894); An Act for Settling the Militia ch. XXIV (1705), 3 Statutes at Large: Being a Collection of all the Laws of Virginia from the First Session of the Legislature, in the Year 1619 335, 339 (William W. Hening ed., 1823); An Act for the Settling and Better Regulation of the Militia ch. II (1723), 4 Statutes at Large: Being a Collection of all the Laws of Virginia from the First Session of the Legislature, in the Year 1619 118, 121 (William W. Hening ed., 1820). But Amici place more weight on those laws than they can rightly bear. The fact that legislatures did not always exercise their authority to seize the arms of individuals who violated the law does not show that legislatures never could do so. Rather, these laws underscore legislatures’ power and discretion to determine when disarmament is warranted. And, as detailed above, Range and Amici’s contention that legislatures lacked the authority to disarm non-violent individuals “flatly misreads the historical record.” Heller, 554 U.S. at 603, 128 S.Ct. 2783.

We believe the Supreme Court’s repeated characterization of Second Amendment rights as belonging to “law-abiding” citizens supports our conclusion that individuals convicted of felony-equivalent crimes, like Range, fall outside “the people” entitled to keep and bear arms.32 See, e.g., Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2122; Heller, 554 U.S. at 635, 128 S.Ct. 2783. As Judge Hardiman explained in his Binderup concurrence, Second Amendment challenges to § 922(g)(1) “require us to decide who count among ‘the people’ entitled to keep and bear arms” because “the Founders understood that not everyone possessed Second Amendment rights.” 836 F.3d at 357 (Hardiman, J., concurring in part); see also Oral Arg. at 49:54 (Amici discussing which individuals fall outside “the people”). Focusing our inquiry on the meaning of “the people” also comports with the Lockean principles that animated Founding-era disarmaments of individuals whose unwillingness to abide by communal norms placed them outside political society. Cf. Heller, 554 U.S. at 580, 128 S.Ct. 2783 (suggesting “the people” refers to “all members of the political community” (emphasis added)); Cornell, Don’t Know Much About History, supra, at 671 (contending the right to keep and bear arms was historically “limited to those members of the polity who were deemed capable of exercising it in a virtuous manner”).

But even if we were to adopt the contrary view, treating Range as covered by “the Second Amendment’s plain text[,]” Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2126, would “yield the same result,” Kanter, 919 F.3d at 452 (Barrett, J., dissenting). Bruen requires the Government to (1) provide relevant historical analogues demonstrating a traditional basis for disarming those who commit felonies and felony-equivalent crimes, and (2) show that the challenger was convicted of a felony or felony-equivalent offense. Cf. Charles, No. 22-CR-154, ––– F.Supp.3d at ––––, 2022 WL 4913900, at *9 (“[R]eading Bruen robotically would require the Government in an as-applied challenge[ ] to find an analogy specific to the crime charged․ That’s absurd.”).

The Government has satisfied its burden on both prongs. First, as discussed above, our Nation’s tradition of firearm regulation permits the disarmament of those who committed felony or felony-equivalent offenses. See Holloway, 948 F.3d at 172 (“We ‘presume the judgment of the legislature is correct and treat any crime subject to § 922(g)(1) as disqualifying unless there is a strong reason to do otherwise.’ ” (quoting Binderup, 836 F.3d at 351)). The Government has established as much through its detailed discussion of our pre-Bruen jurisprudence concerning the “the historical justification for stripping felons [of Second Amendment rights], including those convicted of offenses meeting the traditional definition of a felony.” Appellees’ Supp. Br. 2–3, 7 (quoting Binderup, 836 F. 3d at 348); see also Answering Br. 11–12.

The Government has also shown that Range was convicted of a felony or felony-equivalent offense. Range pleaded guilty to welfare fraud in violation of 62 Pa. Cons. Stat. § 481(a), a misdemeanor punishable by up to five years’ imprisonment. Range’s conviction therefore qualifies as a felony-equivalent offense under both federal law, 18 U.S.C. § 921(a)(20)(B), and traditional legal principles, see Felony, Black’s Law Dictionary (11th ed. 2019). Accordingly, Range may be disarmed consistent with the Second Amendment. See Answering Br. at 16 (citing Hamilton v. Pallozzi, 848 F.3d 614, 627 (4th Cir. 2017))

V. Conclusion

We have conducted a historical review as required by Bruen and we conclude that Range, by illicitly taking welfare money through fraudulent misrepresentation of his income, has demonstrated a rejection of the interests of the state and of the community. He has committed an offense evincing disrespect for the rule of law. As such, his disarmament under 18 U.S.C. § 922(g)(1) is consistent with the Nation’s history and tradition of firearm regulation.

For the above reasons, we will affirm the judgment of the District Court.

FOOTNOTES

FOOTNOTE.

1.   In 2018, Pennsylvania amended § 481(b) so that welfare fraud involving “$1,000 or more” in fraudulently obtained assistance became a “[f]elony of the third degree.” 62 Pa. Cons. Stat. § 481(b) (2018). However, the parties agree that the offense’s categorization at the time of Range’s guilty plea controls for purposes of our analysis.

2.   Congress exercised its discretion to exclude certain categories of offenses from this ban, such as “antitrust violations, unfair trade practices, restraints of trade, or other similar offenses[.]” 18 U.S.C. § 921(a)(20)(A).

3.   For ease of reference, we use the term “felony-equivalent” to refer to these misdemeanors. We do not address whether individuals convicted of misdemeanors carrying lesser punishments can be disarmed consistent with the Second Amendment.

4.   A shotgun that Range’s father had given him as a teenager was also destroyed in the fire. After his father died in 2008, Range came into possession of his father’s pistol, but gave it away within a month.

5.   The relevant factual record has been fully developed, and the appeal raises “purely legal questions upon which an appellate court exercises plenary review,” Comite’ De Apoyo A Los Trabajadores Agricolas v. Perez, 774 F.3d 173, 187 (3d Cir. 2014) (quoting Hudson United Bank v. LiTenda Mortg. Corp., 142 F.3d 151, 159 (3d Cir. 1998)), so we can apply Bruen and resolve this matter without remand, see Hudson, 142 F.3d at 159.

6.   Although we appear to be the first Court of Appeals to address the constitutionality of 18 U.S.C. § 922(g)(1) since the Supreme Court decided Bruen, a number of district courts have done so. See United States v. Young, No. 22-CR-54, 2022 WL 16829260, at *11 (W.D. Pa. Nov. 7, 2022); United States v. Minter, No. 22-CR-135, 2022 WL 10662252, at *6–7 (M.D. Pa. Oct. 18, 2022); United States v. Trinidad, No. 21-CR-398, 2022 WL 10067519, at *3 (D.P.R. Oct. 17, 2022); United States v. Raheem, No. 20-CR-61, 2022 WL 10177684, at *3 (W.D. Ky. Oct. 17, 2022); United States v. Carrero, No. 22-CR-30, ––– F.Supp.3d ––––, ––––, 2022 WL 9348792, at *3 (D. Utah Oct. 14, 2022); United States v. Riley, No. 22-CR-163, ––– F.Supp.3d ––––, ––––, ––––, 2022 WL 7610264, at *10, *13 (E.D. Va. Oct. 13, 2022); United States v. Price, No. 22-CR-97, ––– F.Supp.3d ––––, ––––, 2022 WL 6968457, at *9 (S.D.W. Va. Oct. 12, 2022); United States v. Daniels, No. 3-CR-83, 2022 WL 5027574, at *4 (W.D.N.C. Oct. 4, 2022); United States v. Charles, No. 22-CR-154, ––– F.Supp.3d ––––, ––––, 2022 WL 4913900, at *11 (W.D. Tex. Oct. 3, 2022); United States v. Siddoway, No. 21-CR-205, 2022 WL 4482739, at *2 (D. Idaho Sept. 27, 2022); United States v. Collette, No. 22-CR-141, ––– F.Supp.3d ––––, ––––, 2022 WL 4476790, at *8 (W.D. Tex. Sept. 25, 2022); United States v. Coombes, No. 22-CR-189, ––– F.Supp.3d ––––, ––––, ––––, 2022 WL 4367056, at *8, *11 (N.D. Okla. Sept. 21, 2022); United States v. Hill, No. 21-CR-107, ––– F.Supp.3d ––––, ––––, 2022 WL 4361917, at *3 (S.D. Cal. Sept. 20, 2022); see also United States v. Ridgeway, No. 22-CR-175, 2022 WL 10198823, *2 (S.D. Cal. Oct. 17, 2022); United States v. Cockerham, No. 21-CR-6, 2022 WL 4229314, at *2 (S.D. Miss. Sept. 13, 2022); United States v. Jackson, No. CR 21-51, 2022 WL 4226229, at *3 (D. Minn. Sept. 13, 2022); United States v. Burrell, No. 21-20395, 2022 WL 4096865, at *3 (E.D. Mich. Sept. 7, 2022); United States v. Ingram, No. 18-CR-557, ––– F.Supp.3d ––––, ––––, 2022 WL 3691350, at *3 (D.S.C. Aug. 25, 2022).

7.   While Range’s standing to bring this claim was not challenged by Government nor discussed by the District Court, “we have ‘an independent duty to satisfy ourselves of our jurisdiction ․’ ” Bedrosian v. IRS, 912 F.3d 144, 149 (3d Cir. 2018) (quoting Papotto v. Hartford Life & Acc. Ins. Co., 731 F.3d 265, 269 (3d Cir. 2013)). The party invoking federal jurisdiction must establish the three elements forming “the irreducible constitutional minimum of standing”: injury in fact, causation, and redressability. Lujan v. Defs. of Wildlife, 504 U.S. 555, 560, 112 S.Ct. 2130, 119 L.Ed.2d 351 (1992). “When an individual is subject to [threatened enforcement of a law], an actual arrest, prosecution, or other enforcement action is not a prerequisite to challenging the law.” Susan B. Anthony List v. Driehaus, 573 U.S. 149, 158, 134 S.Ct. 2334, 189 L.Ed.2d 246 (2014). Here, Range met his burden by showing that the Government’s prohibition twice thwarted him from purchasing a firearm and by averring that he would purchase a hunting rifle but for § 922(g)(1). See Parker v. District of Columbia, 478 F.3d 370, 376 (D.C. Cir. 2007) (“The formal process of application and denial, however routine, makes the injury to [the petitioner’s] alleged constitutional interest concrete and particular.”), aff’d sub nom. District of Columbia v. Heller, 554 U.S. 570, 128 S.Ct. 2783, 171 L.Ed.2d 637 (2008); Dearth v. Holder, 641 F.3d 499, 503 (D.C. Cir. 2011) (affirming that the petitioner suffered a cognizable injury where “the federal regulatory scheme thwarts his continuing desire to purchase a firearm”).

8.   On that point, Judge Ambro’s three-judge plurality in Binderup was joined by the seven judges who signed onto Judge Fuentes’s partial concurrence and partial dissent. See Binderup, 836 F.3d at 348–49; id. at 387, 389–90 (Fuentes, J., concurring in part). Judge Hardiman, joined by four other judges, concurred in part and concurred in the judgment. Id. at 357 (Hardiman, J., concurring in part). Judge Hardiman reasoned that under “traditional limitations on the right to keep and bear arms” legislatures could disarm only individuals with a “demonstrated proclivity for violence.” Id.; see also Folajtar v. Att’y Gen., 980 F.3d 897, 912 (3d Cir. 2020) (Bibas, J., dissenting) (stating that “the historical limits on the Second Amendment” permitted legislatures to disarm felons “only if they are dangerous”), cert. denied sub nom. Folajtar v. Garland, ––– U.S. ––––, 141 S. Ct. 2511, 209 L.Ed.2d 546 (2021).

9.   Given Bruen’s focus on history and tradition, Binderup’s multifactored seriousness inquiry no longer applies. In the context of a challenge based upon the challenger’s status post-Binderup, Bruen requires consideration of whether there is a historical foundation for governmental restrictions on firearms possession based on the challenger’s specific status. If that status changes, then the law would no longer apply to that person. Thus, there is still room for “as-applied” challenges even after Bruen.

10.   In Binderup, we had imposed the burden at step one on the challenger, rather than on the government, 836 F.3d at 347, but after Bruen, we note that the government must now meet this burden in the district court, see 142 S. Ct. at 2126 (citing United States v. Boyd, 999 F.3d 171, 185 (3d Cir. 2021)). Because Bruen came down after the Government made its case in the District Court, we look to its filings in the District Court as well as its supplemental briefs on Bruen’s impact to find that it has met its burden.

11.   See also Bruen 142 S. Ct. at 2122 (“[T]he Second and Fourteenth Amendments protect the right of an ordinary, law-abiding citizen to possess a handgun in the home for self-defense.”); id. (“[O]rdinary, law-abiding citizens have a similar right to carry handguns publicly for their self-defense.”); id. at 2125 (explaining petitioners were “law-abiding, adult citizens”); id. at 2133 (describing New York’s argument that “sensitive places where the government may lawfully disarm law-abiding citizens include all places where people typically congregate” (quotations omitted)); id. at 2134 (reiterating that petitioners are “two ordinary, law-abiding, adult citizens”); id. at 2135 n.8 (“[I]n light of the text of the Second Amendment, along with the Nation’s history of firearm regulation, we conclude below that a State may not prevent law-abiding citizens from publicly carrying handguns because they have not demonstrated a special need for self-defense.”); id. at 2138 (“Nor is there any such historical tradition limiting public carry only to those law-abiding citizens who demonstrate a special need for self-defense.”); id. at 2138 n.9 (noting shall-issue public carry licensing laws “do not necessarily prevent ‘law-abiding, responsible citizens’ from exercising their Second Amendment right to public carry” but rather “are designed to ensure only that those bearing arms in the jurisdiction are, in fact, law-abiding, responsible citizens” (quotation omitted)); id. at 2150 (observing “none [of the historical regulations surveyed] operated to prevent law-abiding citizens with ordinary self-defense needs from carrying arms in public for that purpose”); id. at 2156 (“Nor, subject to a few late-in-time outliers, have American governments required law-abiding, responsible citizens to demonstrate a special need for self-protection distinguishable from that of the general community in order to carry arms in public.” (quotations omitted)).

12.   We note that Congress enacted the federal felon-in-possession statute in 1938 and extended it to non-violent offenses in 1961. See United States v. Booker, 644 F.3d 12, 24 (1st Cir. 2011); cf. Freedom from Religion Found., Inc. v. County of Lehigh, 933 F.3d 275, 283 (3d Cir. 2019) (describing a 75-year-old religious symbol as part of “our Nation’s public tradition” and therefore “entitled ․ to a ‘strong presumption of constitutionality’ ” under the First Amendment (quoting Am. Legion v. Am. Humanist Ass’n, ––– U.S. ––––, 139 S. Ct. 2067, 2085, 204 L.Ed.2d 452 (2019))). As explained below, however, the history and tradition of disarming those who have committed offenses demonstrating disrespect for the rule of law dates back to at least the seventeenth century.

13.   It remains the case, of course, that the executive branch also has authority to impose firearms-related directives and regulations consistent with the history and tradition, e.g., in the form of executive orders or through ATF or local executive agencies.

14.   By no means do we suggest that legislatures have carte blanche to disarm anyone who commits any crime. Rather, we decide only that the disarmament of individuals convicted of felony and felony-equivalent offenses comports with the Second Amendment.

15.   Numerous works of legal scholarship have espoused the civic virtue theory of the Second Amendment. See, e.g., Don B. Kates & Clayton E. Cramer, Second Amendment Limitations and Criminological Considerations, 60 Hastings L.J. 1339, 1360 (2008); Saul Cornell & Nathan DeDino, A Well Regulated Right: The Early American Origins of Gun Control, 73 Fordham L. Rev. 487, 492 (2004); Saul Cornell, “Don’t Know Much About History”: The Current Crisis in Second Amendment Scholarship, 29 N. Ky. L. Rev. 657, 672 (2002) [hereinafter Cornell, Don’t Know Much About History]; David Yassky, The Second Amendment: Structure, History, and Constitutional Change, 99 Mich. L. Rev. 588, 626 (2000); Glenn Harlan Reynolds, A Critical Guide to the Second Amendment, 62 Tenn. L. Rev. 461, 480 (1995); Don B. Kates, Jr., The Second Amendment: A Dialogue, 49 L. & Contemp. Probs. 143, 146 (1986); Anthony J. Zarillo III, Comment, Going off Half-Cocked: Opposing as-Applied Challenges to the “Felon-in-Possession” Prohibition of 18 U.S.C. § 922(g)(1), 126 Penn St. L. Rev. 211, 238 (2021). We concur with the civic virtue theory inasmuch as a person’s lack of virtue in the eyes of the community served as a proxy for willingness to disobey the law.

16.   See Folajtar, 980 F.3d at 911 (“Legislatures have always regulated the right to bear arms.”).

17.   When assessing Founding-era precedents, we must assume they derive from a coherent understanding of the right to keep and bear arms shared among the American populace. See Heller, 554 U.S. at 604–05, 128 S.Ct. 2783 (“[T]hat different people of the founding period had vastly different conceptions of the right to keep and bear arms ․ simply does not comport with our longstanding view that the Bill of Rights codified venerable, widely understood liberties.”).

18.   The status-based regulations of this period are repugnant (not to mention unconstitutional), and we categorically reject the notion that distinctions based on race, class, and religion correlate with disrespect for the law or dangerousness. We cite these statutes only to demonstrate legislatures had the power and discretion to use status as a basis for disarmament, and to show that status-based bans did not historically distinguish between violent and non-violent members of disarmed groups.

19.   Again, we cite the repugnant, status-based regulations of an earlier period—disarming individuals on the basis of political affiliation or non-affiliation—merely to demonstrate the Nation’s tradition of imposing categorical, status-based bans on firearm possession.

20.   See Thad W. Tate, The Social Contract in America, 1774–1787: Revolutionary Theory as a Conservative Instrument, 22 Wm. & Mary Q. 375, 376 (1965); see also Gundy v. United States, ––– U.S. ––––, 139 S. Ct. 2116, 2133, 204 L.Ed.2d 522 (2019) (Gorsuch, J., dissenting) (observing “John Locke [was] one of the thinkers who most influenced the framers[ ]”).

21.   Locke based this duty on the consent of those within the political society; however, he contended that mere presence in a territory constituted tacit consent to the laws of the reigning sovereign. See Locke, supra, § 119 (“[I]t is to be considered what shall be understood to be a sufficient declaration of a man’s consent to make him subject to the laws of any government. There is a common distinction of an express and a tacit consent which will concern our present case․ [E]very man that hath any possessions or enjoyment of any part of the dominions of any government doth thereby give his tacit consent and is as far forth obliged to obedience to the laws of that government, during such enjoyment, as any one under it; whether this his possession be of land to him and his heirs for ever, or a lodging only for a week, or whether it be barely travelling freely on the highway; and, in effect, it reaches as far as the very being of anyone within the territories of that government.”).

22.   We cite these laws as evidence of the original understanding of the Second Amendment and the traditions concerning firearms regulation in historical context. Of course, our social and political awareness has obviously evolved significantly since that time, and by today’s standards, the concept of restricting fundamental rights based on political affiliation would be repugnant to the Constitution, including the First Amendment.

23.   See Answering Br. 15 (citing 1 Wayne R. LaFave, Substantive Criminal Law § 2.1(b) (3d ed. 2017); Francis Bacon, Preparation for the Union of Laws of England and Scotland, in 2 The Works of Francis Bacon 160, 163–64 (Basil Montagu ed., Cary & Hart 1844); and 2 Jens David Olin, Wharton’s Criminal Law § 28:2 (16th ed. 2021)).

24.   The Kanter dissent takes issue with this analysis in part because the death penalty was not always imposed. 919 F.3d at 458–62 (Barrett, J., dissenting). How punishments were meted out is beside the point. What matters is the exposure. See id. at 459 (“[M]any crimes remained eligible for the death penalty ․”).

25.   We appreciate that these laws involved the isolated disarmament of the firearm involved in the offense, not a ban on possession as in the other laws we discuss above. Nevertheless, they support the notion that legislatures’ power to strip citizens of their arms was not limited to cases involving violent persons or offenses.

26.   A plaintiff suing the trespasser could alternatively seek the value of the trespasser’s firearms. An Act for the Protection and Security of the Sheep and Other Stock on Tarpaulin Cove Island, Otherwise Called Naushon Island, and on Nennemessett Island, and Several Small Islands Contiguous, Situated in the County of Dukes County § 2 (1790), 1 Private and Special Statutes of the Commonwealth of Massachusetts 258, 259 (Manning & Loring ed., 1805).

27.   We note that history and tradition may indicate that pretextual disarmament is inconsistent with the Second Amendment. Cf. 1 William Blackstone, Commentaries app. *300 (St. George Tucker ed., Birch & Small 1803) (decrying how “[i]n England, the people have been disarmed, generally, under the specious pretext of preserving the game”); Drummond v. Robinson Twp., 9 F.4th 217, 227–29 (3d Cir. 2021). Range does not claim his conviction was pretextual, however, so we leave the issue for another day.

28.   Deference to state legislatures not only accords with longstanding national tradition, but also respects state legislatures’ unique ability to channel local concerns and values into criminal law. See Joshua M. Divine, Statutory Federalism and Criminal Law, 106 Va. L. Rev. 127, 188 (2020) (“[F]ederal reliance on state law disturbs uniformity by baking into federal law variations in state law. But far from being a downside, regional disparity is an asset.”); see also Paul H. Robinson & Tyler Scot Williams, Mapping American Criminal Law: Variations Across the 50 States 4 (2018) (surveying state variation in the incorporation of desert, deterrence, and incapacitation norms into their criminal laws). There is good reason that the criminal codes of arid states like Nevada and Colorado include offenses like diverting irrigation water, Nev. Rev. Stat. § 207.225 (2021), and causing prairie fires, Colo. Rev. Stat. § 18-13-109 (2022), which the code of a state like Maryland does not.In addition to preserving federalism and the separation of powers, upholding legislative determinations of when crimes are sufficiently serious to warrant disarmament avoids forcing “judges to ‘make difficult empirical judgments’ about ‘the costs and benefits of firearms restrictions,’ especially given their ‘lack [of] experience’ in the field.” Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2130 (quoting McDonald, 561 U.S. at 790–91, 130 S.Ct. 3020). And as explained above, judicial determinations of when a crime is sufficiently violent have proven infeasible to apply in other contexts. See Binderup, 836 F.3d at 410 (Fuentes, J., concurring in part).

29.   Some of our esteemed colleagues have expressed concerns about the breadth of state offenses that trigger disarmament under 18 U.S.C. § 922(g)(1). Binderup, 836 F.3d at 372 n.20 (Hardiman, J., concurring in part); Folajtar, 980 F.3d at 921 (Bibas, J., dissenting). But we do not perceive any inherent absurdity in a state’s interest in punishing drug offenders, see Ariz. Rev. Stat. Ann. § 13–3405, or individuals who abuse public services like recycling programs, see Mich. Comp. Laws Ann. § 445.574a(1)(d), or libraries, see 18 Pa. Cons. Stat. Ann. § 3929.1. Indeed, enforcement of the laws cited by our colleagues illustrates why legislatures have chosen to designate them as felonies. Cf. United States v. Bocook, 59 F.3d 167, 167 (4th Cir. 1995) (describing a prosecution for uttering obscene language by means of radio communication when a defendant “broadcast[s] unauthorized radio messages to aircraft and air traffic controllers” in which he “used obscene language, harassed a female air traffic controller, made threats to shoot down aircraft, and transmitted recorded music, weather reports, and warnings about his own activities”).

30.   Moreover, in his supplemental brief, Range appears to raise the issue that a permanent ban on firearm possession lacks a historical basis. See Appellant’s Supp. Br. 3–4. As to arguments concerning the duration of a ban, Congress has addressed it in two ways. First, Congress has exempted any person whose conviction “has been expunged, or set aside or for which a person has been pardoned or has had civil rights restored” from disarmament. § 921(a)(20). Second, Congress also permitted the Bureau of Alcohol, Tobacco, Firearms and Explosives (ATF) to restore individuals’ ability to possess firearms upon consideration of their personal circumstances, criminal record, and the public interest. 18 U.S.C. § 925(c). But these assessments proved so resource intensive for ATF that Congress has refused to fund the program since 1992. See Logan v. United States, 552 U.S. 23, 28 n.1, 128 S.Ct. 475, 169 L.Ed.2d 432 (2007); S. Rep. No. 102-353 (1992). As we previously noted, “[i]f [the petitioner] and others in his position wish to seek recourse, it is to the legislature, and not to the judiciary, that efforts should be directed.” Folajtar, 980 F.3d at 911; Binderup, 836 F.3d at 402-03 (Fuentes, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part).

31.   We note that Amici cited to a 1786 Massachusetts law, but the language Amici references comes from Chapter 46 of the 1785 Act of Massachusetts.

32.   A concern with which district courts have wrestled when assessing the constitutionality of 18 U.S.C. § 922(g)(1) after Bruen is that interpreting “the people” in the Second Amendment to exclude individuals convicted of offenses would deviate from that phrase’s meaning in the First and Fourth Amendments. Cf. Collette, 22-CR-141, ––– F.Supp.3d at ––––, 2022 WL 4476790, at *8 (“[T]his Nation has a longstanding tradition of exercising its right—as a free society—to exclude from ‘the people’ those who squander their rights for crimes and violence.”), with Coombes, No. 22-CR-189, ––– F.Supp.3d at ––––, 2022 WL 4367056, at *4 (“[T]he court declines to carve out felons from the scope of the Second Amendment’s protection of ‘the people.’ ”). But Justice Stevens’s dissent leveled that very criticism against the Heller majority: “[T]he Court limits the protected class to ‘law-abiding, responsible citizens.’ But the class of persons protected by the First and Fourth Amendments is not so limited; for even felons (and presumably irresponsible citizens as well) may invoke the protections of those constitutional provisions.” 554 U.S. at 644, 128 S.Ct. 2783 (Stevens, J., dissenting). However, our reasoning applies solely to the Second Amendment and does not imply any limitation on the rights of individuals convicted of felony and felony-equivalent offenses under other provisions of the Constitution. source


Other Important 2nd Amendment Cases

felons can posses gun cases

 

Federal Judge Tosses Gun Possession Case Against Convicted Felon United States v. Bullock

Third Circuit Holds that a Nonviolent felon May Not Be Stripped of Second Amendment Rights.


 

error: Content is protected !!